shǒuyè>> wénxué>> xiē 'ěr · Michel Foucault
  《 fēng diān wén míng shūshí jiān kuà yòu liù bǎi niánhuà shì cóng " fēng rén " zài shǐ tái shàng de chū xiàn tán zhōng shì suí zhe fēng bìng de xiāo tuìfēng rén kāi shǐ dài fēng bìng huàn zhěchéng wéi shè huì pái chì de xīn duì xiàngrán hòu shì shù zhè zhǒng pái chì / zhì de zhǒng biàn xíngwén xīng shí shí -- shí liù shì shì yòng " rén chuán " fàng zhú menjiù xiàng shùn tóu xiōng wán ); diǎn shí shí shì shì men dāng " shè huì " zuì fànmáng liú guān jìn shōu róng suǒjiào " jìn "; méng shí shí shì shì men dāng " wēn " lái jiào " kǒng "; zhōng diǎn shì shí jiǔ shì fēng rén zuì fàn fēn kāidāng bìng rén kàn dài " zhèng cháng rén " shí xíng " zhì bìng jiù rén " de " rén dào zhù "。 zhè yàng cái xíng chéng xiàn dài de jīng shén bìng yuàn


  Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason, by Michel Foucault, is an examination of the ideas, practices, institutions, art and literature relating to madness in Western history. It is the abridged English edition of Histoire de la folie à l'âge classique, originally published in 1961 under the title Folie et déraison. Histoire de la folie à l'âge classique. A full translation titled The History of Madness was published by Routledge in June 2006. This was Foucault's first major book, written while he was the Director of the Maison de France in Sweden.
  
  Foucault begins his history in the Middle Ages, noting the social and physical exclusion of lepers. He argues that with the gradual disappearance of leprosy, madness came to occupy this excluded position. The ship of fools in the 15th century is a literary version of one such exclusionary practice, the practice of sending mad people away in ships. However, during the Renaissance, madness was regarded as an all-abundant phenomenon because humans could not come close to the Reason of God. As Cervantes' Don Quixote, all humans are weak to desires and dissimulation. Therefore, the insane, understood as those who had come too close to God's Reason, were accepted in the middle of society. It is not before the 17th century, in a movement which Foucault famously describes as the Great Confinement, that "unreasonable" members of the population systematically were locked away and institutionalized. In the 18th century, madness came to be seen as the obverse of Reason, that is, as having lost what made them human and become animal-like and therefore treated as such. It is not before 19th century that madness was regarded as a mental illness that should be cured, e.g. Philippe Pinel, Freud. A few professional historians have argued that the large increase in confinement did not happen in 17th but in the 19th century. Critics argue that this undermines the central argument of Foucault, notably the link between the Age of Enlightenment and the suppression of the insane.
  
  However, Foucault scholars have shown that Foucault was not talking about medical institutions designed specifically for the insane but about the creation of houses of confinement for social outsiders, including not only the insane but also vagrants, unemployed, impoverished, and orphaned, and what effect those general houses of confinement had on the insane and perceptions of Madness in western society. Furthermore, Foucault goes to great lengths to demonstrate that while this "confinement" of social outcasts was a generally European phenomenon, it had a unique development in France and distinct developments in the other countries that the confinement took place in, such as Germany and England, disproving complaints that Foucault takes French events to generalize the history of madness in the West. A few of the historians critical of its historiography, such as Roy Porter, also began to concur with these refutations and discarded their own past criticisms to acknowledge the revolutionary nature of Foucault's book.
  zhè gài shì xiě guò de zuì jiē jìn " wán měi " de zhù zuòlěng jùn de miáo xiě liè de " shū qíng xīn ", zhì de fēn tòu de lùn fǎnxǐng chōng mǎn zhāng de fāng shì duì zuì chū tái wān bǎn de fān zhě yòu zuò liǎo jīng xīn de xiū gǎishǐ xiàn zài zhè běn lùn zhǔn què xìng hái shì liú chàng xìng kān chēng jiā dāng rán fān de zhì liàng shì jiàn zài zuò zhě duì xiǎng de quán miàn yán jiū de chǔ shàng dezhè diǎn qià qià shì xiàn zài duō fān suǒ quē de guòjiāng discipline wéi " guī xùn ", réng yòu " zào " zhī xiánér xiàn yòu de " " què gèng tiē qiē jìng zài cǎi wéi zhè zuò " "( suǒ zhè gài niàn bìng fēi zhě suǒ yánshì de " chuàng ")。


  Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison is a book written by the philosopher Michel Foucault. Originally published in 1975 in France under the title Surveiller et punir: Naissance de la Prison, it was translated into English in 1977. It is an examination of the social and theoretical mechanisms behind the massive changes that occurred in western penal systems during the modern age. It focuses on historical documents from France, but the issues it examines are relevant to every modern western society. It is considered a seminal work, and has influenced many theorists and artists.
  
  Foucault challenges the commonly accepted idea that the prison became the consistent form of punishment due to humanitarian concerns of reformists, although he does not deny those. He does so by meticulously tracing out the shifts in culture that led to the prison's dominance, focusing on the body and questions of power. Prison is a form used by the "disciplines", a new technological power, which can also be found, according to Foucault, in schools, hospitals, military barracks, etc. The main ideas of Discipline and Punish can be grouped according to its four parts: torture, punishment, discipline and prison.
  
  Torture
  
  Foucault begins the book by contrasting two forms of penalty: the violent and chaotic public torture of Robert-François Damiens who was convicted of attempted regicide in the late 18th century, and the highly regimented daily schedule for inmates from an early 19th century prison. These examples provide a picture of just how profound the change in western penal systems were after less than a century. Foucault wants the reader to consider what led to these changes. How did western culture shift so radically?
  
  To answer this question, he begins by examining public torture itself. He argues that the public spectacle of torture was a theatrical forum that served several intended and unintended purposes for society. The intended purposes were:
  
   * Reflecting the violence of the original crime onto the convict's body for all to see.
   * Enacting the revenge upon the convict's body, which the sovereign seeks for having been injured by the crime. Foucault argues that the law was considered an extension of the sovereign's body, and so the revenge must take the form of harming the convict's body.
  
  Some unintended consequences were:
  
   * Providing a forum for the convict's body to become a focus of sympathy and admiration.
   * Creating a site of conflict between the masses and the sovereign at the convict's body. Foucault notes that public executions often led to riots in support of the prisoner.
  
  Thus, he argues, the public execution was ultimately an ineffective use of the body, qualified as non-economical. As well, it was applied non-uniformly and haphazardly. Hence, its political cost was too high. It was the antithesis of the more modern concerns of the state: order and generalization.
  Punishment
  
  The switch to prison was not immediate. There was a more graded change, though it ran its course rapidly. Prison was preceded by a different form of public spectacle. The theater of public torture gave way to public chain gangs. Punishment became "gentle", though not for humanitarian reasons, Foucault suggests. He argues that reformists were unhappy with the unpredictable, unevenly distributed nature of the violence the sovereign would inflict on the convict. The sovereign's right to punish was so disproportionate that it was ineffective and uncontrolled. Reformists felt the power to punish and judge should become more evenly distributed, the state's power must be a form of public power. This, according to Foucault, was of more concern to reformists than humanitarian arguments.
  
  Out of this movement towards generalized punishment, a thousand "mini-theatres" of punishment would have been created wherein the convicts' bodies would have been put on display in a more ubiquitous, controlled, and effective spectacle. Prisoners would have been forced to do work that reflected their crime, thus repaying society for their infractions. This would have allowed the public to see the convicts' bodies enacting their punishment, and thus to reflect on the crime. But these experiments lasted less than twenty years.
  
  Foucault argues that this theory of "gentle" punishment represented the first step away from the excessive force of the sovereign, and towards more generalized and controlled means of punishment. But he suggests that the shift towards prison that followed was the result of a new "technology" and ontology for the body being developed in the 18th century, the "technology" of discipline, and the ontology of "man as machine."
  Discipline
  
  The emergence of prison as the form of punishment for every crime grew out of the development of discipline in the 18th and 19th centuries, according to Foucault. He looks at the development of highly refined forms of discipline, of discipline concerned with the smallest and most precise aspects of a person's body. Discipline, he suggests, developed a new economy and politics for bodies. Modern institutions required that bodies must be individuated according to their tasks, as well as for training, observation, and control. Therefore, he argues, discipline created a whole new form of individuality for bodies, which enabled them to perform their duty within the new forms of economic, political, and military organizations emerging in the modern age and continuing to today.
  
  The individuality that discipline constructs (for the bodies it controls) has four characteristics, namely it makes individuality which is:
  
   * Cellular—determining the spatial distribution of the bodies
   * Organic—ensuring that the activities required of the bodies are "natural" for them
   * Genetic—controlling the evolution over time of the activities of the bodies
   * Combinatory—allowing for the combination of the force of many bodies into a single massive force
  
  Foucault suggests this individuality can be implemented in systems that are officially egalitarian, but use discipline to construct non-egalitarian power relations:
  
   Historically, the process by which the bourgeoisie became in the course of the eighteenth century the politically dominant class was masked by the establishment of an explicit, coded and formally egalitarian juridical framework, made possible by the organization of a parliamentary, representative regime. But the development and generalization of disciplinary mechanisms constituted the other, dark side of these processes. The general juridical form that guaranteed a system of rights that were egalitarian in principle was supported by these tiny, everyday, physical mechanisms, by all those systems of micro-power that are essentially non-egalitarian and asymmetrical that we call the disciplines. (222)
  
  Foucault's argument is that discipline creates "docile bodies", ideal for the new economics, politics and warfare of the modern industrial age—bodies that function in factories, ordered military regiments, and school classrooms. But, to construct docile bodies the disciplinary institutions must be able to a) constantly observe and record the bodies they control, b) ensure the internalization of the disciplinary individuality within the bodies being controlled. That is, discipline must come about without excessive force through careful observation, and molding of the bodies into the correct form through this observation. This requires a particular form of institution, which Foucault argues, was exemplified by Jeremy Bentham's Panopticon, which was never actually built.
  
  The Panopticon was the ultimate realization of a modern disciplinary institution. It allowed for constant observation characterized by an "unequal gaze"; the constant possibility of observation. Perhaps the most important feature of the panopticon was that it was specifically designed so that the prisoner could never be sure whether s/he was being observed. The unequal gaze caused the internalization of disciplinary individuality, and the docile body required of its inmates. This means one is less likely to break rules or laws if they believe they are being watched, even if they are not. Thus, prison, and specifically those that follow the model of the Panopticon, provide the ideal form of modern punishment. Foucault argues that this is why the generalized, "gentle" punishment of public work gangs gave way to the prison. It was the ideal modernization of punishment, so its eventual dominance was natural.
  
  Having laid out the emergence of the prison as the dominant form of punishment, Foucault devotes the rest of the book to examining its precise form and function in our society, to lay bare the reasons for its continued use, and question the assumed results of its use.
  Prison
  
  In examining the construction of the prison as the central means of criminal punishment, Foucault builds a case for the idea that prison became part of a larger “carceral system” that has become an all-encompassing sovereign institution in modern society. Prison is one part of a vast network, including schools, military institutions, hospitals, and factories, which build a panoptic society for its members. This system creates “disciplinary careers” (Discipline and Punish, 300) for those locked within its corridors. It is operated under the scientific authority of medicine, psychology, and criminology. Moreover, it operates according to principles that ensure that it “cannot fail to produce delinquents.” (Discipline and Punish, 266). Delinquency, indeed, is produced when social petty crime (such as taking wood in the lord's lands) is no longer tolerated, creating a class of specialized "delinquents" acting as the police's proxy in surveillance of society.
  
  The structures Foucault chooses to use as his starting positions help highlight his conclusions. In particular, his choice as a perfect prison of the penal institution at Mettray helps personify the carceral system. Within it is included the Prison, the School, the Church, and the work-house (industry)—all of which feature heavily in his argument. The prisons at Neufchatel, Mettray, and Mettray Netherlands were perfect examples for Foucault, because they, even in their original state, began to show the traits Foucault was searching for. They showed the body of knowledge being developed about the prisoners, the creation of the 'delinquent' class, and the disciplinary careers emerging.
   gěi wǎng mín men de fēng diàn yóu jiàn
  
   qīn 'ài de zhōng guó de wǎng yǒu
     jiā hǎo
  
     shǒu xiān duì yòu zhè yàng huì néng gòu jiā duì huà biǎo shì wàn fēn róng xìngzuì jìn tīng shuō de zhù zuò zài guì guó fān chū bǎn liǎo hěn duōjìn guǎn néng zài xiǎng shòu yóu 'ér dài lái de bǎn quán rùnér qiě yòu hěn fēn hái shǔ dào bǎndàn duì de rén lái shuōmíng néng gòu wéi gèng duō de rén suǒ zhī xiǎo jìng shì jiàn hǎo shì
  
     yòu péng yǒu shuō de zhù zuò wén huì yǐng xiǎng liǎo yuè zhè diǎn yào shuō míng xiàyīn wéi jiǎng de xìngquán zhèng zhì děng děng huà jiǎng jiādōu míng bái zhǐ shì dōng chě néng zhǎo dào denéng xiǎng dào dedōu chě shànghào chēng " zhī shí kǎo xué ", xiǎn lái tóu néng duō hùn xiē gǎo fèi xíng zhōng jiù jiǎn dān de shì qíng gěi gǎo liǎozài xiān xiàng jiā zhì qiàn
  
     shuō liáng xīn huà de zhù zuò hái shì tǐng yòu zhuī qiú de de zhuī qiú jiù shì xiǎng wéi tiān xià xiàng ràng rén qiáo de ruò zhě men tóng xìng liànfēng shénme de tǎo gōng dàoràng shǐ shuō huàjiē jiē xiē suǒ wèi " zhèng cháng rén " de lǎo ràng jiā kāi men de huà kàn kàntóng shí zài bēicóng kuài shēng huó
  
     shuō shí huà shì tóng xìng liànzhè men yědōu yòu suǒ 'ěr wén guǒ ràng kàn dào měi méi shì diǎn 'ér gǎn jué dōuméi yòu yào shì kàn dào piào liàng de xiǎo huǒ 'ér jiù huì dòng láixiàng zhè yàng de rénzài zhěng rén lèi shè huì zhōng suǒ zhàn de hái xiǎoyòu rén shuōtóng xìng liàn shì " shè huì chǒu 'è xiàn xiàng ", zhè jiǎn zhí shì rèn de xiā chě men zhī dào zhè tóng xìng liàn shì tiān shēng de shì hòu tiān xué chū lái dezhè jiù gēn men shēng xià lái shì nán dejiù shì nán deshì de jiù shì de yàngér qiěshuí guī dìng liǎo nán de zhǎo de de zhǎo nán de guǒ men liǎng nán rén zhēn xīn xiāng 'ài jiù shì men liǎ rén de shì 'éryòu 'ài zhe shuí liǎo men huān rén men guǎn guò men yòu píng shénme lái guǎn men men huān rénjiù ràng men huān rénzhè tài dào liǎo men míng míng huān rénpiān ràng men gēn rén hǎozhè shì zhǎo zuì shòu shuō men tóng xìng liàn chuán rǎn 'ài bìngzhè dǎo shì shì shí jiù shì yīn wéi liǎo 'ài bìng de men gēn rén shì gǎo chū xìng bìng lái liǎo zěn me jiù shuō liǎo zài shū zhōng céng jīng chǎn shì guò yǔn liǎng nán rén jié hūn de wén míngjiù suàn shì zhēn zhèng de wén míngtīng shuō měi guó gōng lín dùn shàng rèn hòu de xiàng lìng shì guān guó jīng de shì guān shì jiè píng deér shì guān měi jūn rén tóng xìng liàn huà dezhè xiǎo hái shì mán jiě men zhè xiē xiǎng jiā de
  
     zuì jìn tīng shuōzhōng guó yòu zhe yōu jiǔ de tóng xìng liàn shǐliú chuán jiǔ de duàn xiùfēn táo děng měi de tóng xìng liàn chuán shuōzài guì guó de míng zhùhóng lóu mèngzhōng yòu miáo xiě duì shàonián de tóng xìng liàn shì desuǒ xiāng xìn men dāng zhōng yòu duō xiàng zhè yàng de rénpéng yǒu men guǒ men zài shēng huó zhōng dào cháo fěng qièmò huī xīnbié shī yào zhī dàozhè shì shénme diū liǎn de shì wǎng jīn lái yòu duō shǎo yīng xióng háo jiédōushì men yàng de rénér qiěyào yòu zài tiān shàng wéi men jìnwéi men jiā yóu
  
     lìng wài hái yán jiū fēng cháng shēng huó lǎo yòu rén shuō bié rén: " hēngfēng shén jīng bìng! " zhè shì jiǎng dào de fèi huà men de jiù shì fēng jiù shì shén jīng bìng men shuō shí me jiù shì shénme 'ér yòu shì 'ér 'ā men shuō cǎi xiān shēng shì fēng sòng jìn liǎo fēng rén yuàn shì qǐng kàn kànyòu shuí gǎn shuō cǎi xiān shēng gèng qīng xǐngduì shì jiè kàn gèng tòuguì guó yòu běn xiǎo shuō jiàokuáng rén 》, biān jiù shì jiǎng fēng de shì hòu lái bié réndōu shuō zhè fēng shì " fǎn fēng jiàn de dǒu shì "。 suǒ bié wéi " zhèng cháng " jiù shì shénme hǎo shì 'ér shuō guò liǎosuǒ wèi " zhèng cháng ", guò jiù shì lìng zhǒng xíng shì de fēng diānshuō bái liǎo huǒ 'ér dōushì fēng shuí bié shuō shuí men shuō shì fēng cóng lìng jiǎo shuō men hái shì fēng zán men zhè xiē fēng men huó zài zhè shì jiè shàng píng gòng chù jiù chéng liǎo guò dāng rán huà néng shuō jué duì liǎoyòu xiē fēng tǎo yànjiè zhe fēng jìn 'ér xiā zhēténg men guān lái hái shì duì de de péng yǒu 'ā 'ěr sài fēng liǎo zhī hòu lǎo gěi qiā liǎohòu lái bèi guān zài fēng rén yuàn zhí dào xiǎng lái tòng xīn 'ā tiān cái jiù zhè yàng …。 zhì shǎo xīn kuài shí tóu luò liǎo lián lǎo qiā liǎopéng yǒu gèng dào zāiyào shì liú shénràng gěi qiā liǎohái gěi cháng mìng cái jiào kuī
  
     chú liǎo shàng shuō de hái chàng " diān fēng yàn ", yòu chēng zuò " duān yàn " deshuō bái liǎojiù shì yào " shuǎng dāi liǎo "! guò zhè " shuǎng " dǎo dìng shì zhǐ píng cháng de xiē xiǎng shòu lái bèng jiù shì cháng dào kǒng de shuǎng shòu nüè dài jiù shì tòng de shuǎngé luó yòu xiě xiǎo shuō de lǎo jiào tuó tuǒ shuō zuì shuǎng de shí hòu jiù shì chōu yáng jiǎo fēng de shí hòu shēng dōuzài zhuī qiú zhì de shuǎngshénme fāng shì dōuchéngzhǐ yào gāo xīng jiù xíngzhǐ yào shuǎng jiù xínghuó zhe de shí hòu yòu shí yòu jié zhì diǎn 'ér jìn 'ér shàng lái de shí hòujiù yòu diǎn piāo piāo ránhěn shuǎng deyòu huí chū mén ràng chē gěi zhuàng liǎorén jiā sòng jìn yuànyòu fēn zhōng jué yào liǎoāi zhǒng gǎn jué hǎo shuǎng zhì zhēn de shí hòu fèn 'ér shuǎng jiù gèng béng liǎocháng yán dào " xiān ", zhēn shì hěn yòu dào de lie
  
     dāng rán chàng jiā quán gēn xuézhuī qiú de shuǎngshàng liǎo yǐn qīng jiā dàng chǎn jiù biàn chéng qióng shuǎng liǎozhè zhǒng shuǎng cháng tài zhuī qiú xìng 'ài de shuǎng xiǎo xīn liǎo xìng bìng 'ài shénme deduì jiàn kāng chéng xīn 'āi chē zhuàng gèng shì chī bǎo liǎo chēng dezhè zhǒng shuǎng 'ér qiú guò jiā huǒ 'ér yào zhuī qiú shuǎng shì tǐng róng dezhǐ yào 'ài zhe bié rén de shì 'érjiǎng jiū diǎn 'ér rén wèi shēng sǔn hài bié rén de jiàn kāng de jiàn kāng wéi sǔn hài 'ān dìng tuán jié jiù xíng liǎozěn me jué shuǎng jiù zěn me láitóng xìng liàn hǎoràng bié rén shuō shì " fēng " zǒu de ràng bié rén shuō jìngrén shēng duǎnyào jìn suǒ yòu néng de shuǎngcái shì gèng de 'ā
  
     péng yǒu menràng men gòng miǎn
  
                              men zuì qián chéng de
                              xiē 'ěr ·
  
     shùn biàn shuō xiàchén bēi zhǎo dào yào gěi zhōng guó wǎng yǒu fēng " mèi 'ér "。 dǒng zhōng wényòu diǎn yóu chén bēi pāi zhe xiōngpú shuō fān chǒu de shuǐ píngyòu diǎn 'ér 'èr dāo zài zhè yìng pào niùbùguòzhǐ hǎo xiě liǎo shàng miàn de huà guǒ wǎng yǒu men chǒu zhe duì jìn 'ér dōushì chén bēi de sōu zhù qiān wàn bié zhǎo
  
                              xiē 'ěr ·
                              yòu
shǒuyè>> wénxué>> xiē 'ěr · Michel Foucault