首頁>> 文學>> 动物>> 達爾文 Charles Darwin   英國 United Kingdom   漢諾威王朝   (1809年二月12日1882年四月19日)
物種起源 On the Origin of Species
  達爾文在《物種起源》中提出兩個理論。第一,他認為所有的動植物都是由較早期、較原始的形式演變而來;其次,他認為生物演化是通過自然選擇而來。
  
  其理論重點如下:物種並非一成不變,而是會隨環境變動而改變;生物的演化是長時間連續性的緩慢改變,不是突然性的劇變;同一類生物有着共同的祖先,例如哺乳類是由同一個祖先演變而來;生物族群會隨着繁殖而擴大,並超過其生存空間與食物供應的極限,引起個體間的競爭;不適應環境的個體會被淘汰,適者才能生存,並繁衍後代。
  《物種起源》-作者簡介
  
  達爾文(Charles Darwin,1809~1882):英國偉大的科學家、博物學家,進化論的奠基人。生於英國一個名醫世傢。兒時“除打獵、養狗、抓老鼠以外,無所事事”(達爾文父親語)。後因結識植物學家亨斯羅後對博物學産生興趣。1831年參加 “比格爾號”艦的全球遠航,1842年首次提出 “物種進化理論”。
  《物種起源》-撰寫背景
  
  在達爾文那個時代,人們普遍都接受創造論,相信上帝創造世界、並一次就創造出所有的生物,同時上帝也賦予每種生物各自的角色,而每個物種的設計都非常完美,所以物種是永恆固定不變的。地層中發現的化石是古代地球曾經遭遇大洪水的證據,那些化石就是沒有登上諾亞方舟的動物。地球的歷史大約衹有六千年左右,這是經由從亞當和夏娃開始後的人類世代所推算的時間。
  
  達爾文1809年生於英格蘭舒茲伯利 (Shrewsbury)。達爾文從小就對礦物和動物有興趣。1831年他從劍橋大學神學院畢業,然而他還是對地質學及生物學比較有興趣。1831年12月達爾文參加了海軍艦艇小獵犬號前往南美洲從事自然調查研究工作;最初他在南美海岸調查,並多次進入南美洲西邊的加拉巴哥群島,經過太平洋到達新西蘭、澳大利亞及南非,然後又回到南美洲,直到1836年10月纔回到英國。
  
  1836年10月,達爾文回到英國後了22年時間撰寫《物種起源》一書。1859年11月24日,達爾文的《物種起源》一書出版。這本書極大地衝擊了“神創論”,引起教會激烈反對,但也得到許多有識之士的贊賞和維護。此後,達爾文的學說在全球廣泛傳播,不斷深入人心。19世紀70年代,達爾文的學說傳入中國。
  《物種起源》-理論形成
  
  達爾文在南美洲考察時,在安第斯山山頂上發現海洋生物的化石,讓他感到睏惑。在小獵犬號啓航時,達爾文曾帶了一本英國地質學家萊爾所著的《地質學原理》;萊爾認為地球的地形、地貌是經過長時間不斷的細微變化的結果,萊爾相信風力、雨滴、冰雪等微小的力量,持續千萬年後就可以完全改變地表的形貌。達爾文本人也相信,衹要時間足夠,無法察覺的細微改變也可以造成巨大的變化。達爾文推算白堊紀中期距今約有三億年左右的歷史,持續長時間微小的地震等自然因素使得原來在海中的生物遺跡能在高山上發現。
  
  在加拉巴哥群島考察時,達爾文發現每個島嶼上的陸龜及雀鳥並沒有很大的差異,但又有些許的不同。他又發現加拉巴哥群島的生物與南美洲大陸的種類非常相似;於是他開始懷疑島上生物可能有共同的祖先,他們之間的差異是由於千百年來適應各個島嶼不同環境的結果。每一個物種都是一些細微的變化在無數個世代的過程中産生的結果。
  1《物種起源》
  
  生物進化在當時並不是新的概念。1809年時,法國動物學家拉馬剋便提出:當環境改變時,物種會調適發展自己的器官來適應環境,常用的器官會發育變大、不用的器官會逐漸退化,並且這一代獲取的改變會遺傳給下一代;但沒有科學證據可以證明“用進廢退”和“獲得性特徵可遺傳”的假說。後來達爾文又從英國人口學者馬爾薩斯所著的《人口論》得到靈感;馬爾薩斯認為:人類糧食的生産永遠無法趕上人口的增加,致使糧食供不應求,進而發生饑荒或戰爭,導致一部分人口死亡。達爾文以此聯想到生物演化發生的機製:演化是生存競爭中自由淘汰的結果,食物與空間等資源有限,衹有最適應環境的個體才能生存下來,延續族群。
  
  “天擇”的概念逐漸在達爾文的五年環球考察過程中形成。在1836年回到英國後,達爾文慢慢將他的看法寫成文章,然而沒有發表。大部分科學家認為,達爾文遲了很久纔發表他的作品,原因之一就是擔心自己的思想對於當時的社會來說過於激進。1858年,達爾文接到在馬來群島調查的博物學者華萊士有關物種形成的文章;華萊士對於物種形成的看法與他有很多相似之處,增加了達爾文對其學說的信心。於是兩人在1858年的倫敦皇傢科學年會中,以兩人共同具名的方式,發表有關物種形成的看法。接着達爾文在1859年發表了《物種起源》。
  《物種起源》-影響
  
  引起爭議
  
  達爾文的進化論當時引起了廣泛的爭議,被基督教會視為異端邪說,西方社會也對達爾文冷嘲熱諷。不僅上帝創造萬物的說法被推翻,人類也被形容為千百年來殘酷的生存競爭所形成的産物,還指出人與其他哺乳動物有着共同祖先,這在當時保守的社會是相當大的震撼。
  
  毫無疑問,它給當時的社會帶來的是霹靂般的震蕩,像一顆炸彈一樣投到“神學陣地的心髒上”,引起了整個世界特別是英國保守勢力和宗教神學勢力的極端驚恐和狂怒,譴責的聲浪鋪天蓋地而來。教會勢力和老派學者攻擊《物種起源》是“惡作劇”,違背了上帝的啓示,是一部“魔鬼的聖經”,而達爾文本人則是“英國最危險的人”。
  
  達爾文預見到這本書的出版一定會引起激烈的爭論,因此,他把樣書分送給萊爾、鬍剋、赫胥黎及格雷等科學家,以爭取他們的支持和鼓勵。
  
  學術地位
  
  本書是生物學史上的經典著作。1859年11月24日《物種起源》出版,當天即被搶購一空。這主要因為《物種起源》也受到英國和其他國傢一些學者的積極支持,像英國的 T.H.赫胥黎、德國的E.海剋爾等。《物種起源》出版,第一次把生物學建立在完全科學的基礎上,以全新的生物進化思想推翻了“神創論”和“物種不變”理論,生物普遍進化的思想以及“物競天擇,適者生存”的進化機製成為學術界、思想界的公論。在書中,達爾文提出了一個又一個令人震驚的論斷:生命衹有一個祖先,因為生命都起源於一個原始細胞的開端;生物是從簡單到復雜、從低級到高級逐步發展而來的,生物在進化中不斷進行着生存鬥爭,進行着自然選擇。由此,達爾文的生物進化論被稱為19世紀自然科學的三大發現之一,《物種起源》所提及的許多觀點已成為人盡皆知的常識。
  《物種起源》-面臨挑戰
  
  達爾文並不認為自己的理論完美無缺,他也有很多睏惑。自《物種起源》出版100年間,進化論先後面臨科學發展帶來的以下幾個“挑戰”:
  
  在《物種起源》發表6年後,德國學者海剋爾依據進化論思想畫出了一棵“生命之樹”,用“樹”來形象描繪生物進化歷史。然而,由於形態和生理特徵的進化極其復雜,加上化石資料不夠完整,“生命之樹”難以反映復雜生物進化歷史的全貌。在這種情況下,現代分子生物學的重要性就顯現出來。現在科研人員可以通過比較DNA序列來研究不同生物之間的進化關係,構建 “進化樹”。病毒等微生物“網狀”進化結構的發現對此前的進化理論提出疑問,促使其進一步完善。
  
  達爾文進化論的一個重要觀點是漸變論,即物種是通過微小的優勢變異逐漸改進的,突變是很少的,但最令達爾文睏惑的是寒武紀物種大爆發。中國科學家通過對雲南澄江動物群化石的發現和研究,揭示了寒武紀物種大爆發的整體輪廓,證實幾乎所有動物的祖先都曾經站在同一起跑綫上。這一發現在很大程度上說明,生物的進化並非總是漸進的,而是漸進與躍進並存的過程。
  
  達爾文在《物種起源》一書中比較多地推崇自然選擇,認為生物進化中有害的突變比較多,有利的突變很少,而經過長期的進化過程,有利的突變經過自然選擇終於占了上風。但後來科學研究發現,物種的有害突變和有利突變都不是很多,多的是對於自然選擇來說不好也不壞的中性突變,這後一類突變與進化的關聯還有待深入細緻的研究。
  《物種起源》-評價
  
  如果要評選過去的一千年來最重要的著作,達爾文的《物種起源》無疑問是一個強有力的競爭者。它不僅為生物學奠定了堅實的理論基礎,也影響了人類社會的幾乎所有方面。
  
  生物進化論是研究生物進化、生物發展規律以及如何運用這些規律的科學,是生物學的一個重要部門。進化論一詞最初是拉馬剋提出。達爾文的《物種起源》一書奠定了進化論的科學基礎。在《物種起源》發表前的歐洲,接受進化論思想的人非常少,儘管當時人們已經不再生活於中世紀愚昧的宗教統治中,伽利略和哥白尼的太陽中心說已經確立300多年,但人們仍然相信《聖經》中的上帝創世說。人和一切生物都是上帝創造的,這是天經地義,毋庸置疑的。但是這本書,大膽地嚮上帝創世說進行了挑戰,並從根本上撼動了《聖經》的基礎。
  
  這部著作的問世,第一次把生物學建立在完全科學的基礎上,確定了物種的變異性和承續性,以全新的“生物進化”思想,推翻了那種把動植物看作彼此毫無聯繫的、偶然的、神造的、不變的東西的觀點,也就是“神創論”和物種不變的理論。達爾文以自然界的規律代替了“造物主的智慧”,並直接涉及人類自身的由來及歷史,使宗教的基本信念發生了動搖,導致科學與宗教間的更深刻衝突。


  Charles Darwin's On the Origin of Species, published on 24 November 1859, is a work of scientific literature which is considered to be the foundation of evolutionary biology. Its full title was On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life. For the sixth edition of 1872, the short title was changed to The Origin of Species. Darwin's book introduced the theory that populations evolve over the course of generations through a process of natural selection. It presented a body of evidence that the diversity of life arose by common descent through a branching pattern of evolution. Darwin included evidence that he had gathered on the Beagle expedition in the 1830s and his subsequent findings from research, correspondence, and experimentation.
  
  Various evolutionary ideas had already been proposed to explain new findings in biology. There was growing support for such ideas among dissident anatomists and the general public, but during the first half of the 19th century the English scientific establishment was closely tied to the Church of England, while science was part of natural theology. Ideas about the transmutation of species were controversial as they conflicted with the beliefs that species were unchanging parts of a designed hierarchy and that humans were unique, unrelated to animals. The political and theological implications were intensely debated, but transmutation was not accepted by the scientific mainstream.
  
  The book was written for non-specialist readers and attracted widespread interest upon its publication. As Darwin was an eminent scientist, his findings were taken seriously and the evidence he presented generated scientific, philosophical, and religious discussion. The debate over the book contributed to the campaign by T.H. Huxley and his fellow members of the X Club to secularise science by promoting scientific naturalism. Within two decades there was widespread scientific agreement that evolution, with a branching pattern of common descent, had occurred, but scientists were slow to give natural selection the significance that Darwin thought appropriate. During the "eclipse of Darwinism" from the 1880s to the 1930s, various other mechanisms of evolution were given more credit. With the development of the modern evolutionary synthesis in the 1930s and 1940s, Darwin's concept of evolutionary adaptation through natural selection became central to modern evolutionary theory, now the unifying concept of the life sciences.
  When on board H.M.S. 'Beagle,' as naturalist, I was much struck with certain facts in the distribution of the inhabitants of South America, and in the geological relations of the present to the past inhabitants of that continent. These facts seemed to me to throw some light on the origin of species--that mystery of mysteries, as it has been called by one of our greatest philosophers. On my return home, it occurred to me, in 1837, that something might perhaps be made out on this question by patiently accumulating and reflecting on all sorts of facts which could possibly have any bearing on it. After five years' work I allowed myself to speculate on the subject, and drew up some short notes; these I enlarged in 1844 into a sketch of the conclusions, which then seemed to me probable: from that period to the present day I have steadily pursued the same object. I hope that I may be excused for entering on these personal details, as I give them to show that I have not been hasty in coming to a decision.
   My work is now nearly finished; but as it will take me two or three more years to complete it, and as my health is far from strong, I have been urged to publish this Abstract. I have more especially been induced to do this, as Mr. Wallace, who is now studying the natural history of the Malay archipelago, has arrived at almost exactly the same general conclusions that I have on the origin of species. Last year he sent to me a memoir on this subject, with a request that I would forward it to Sir Charles Lyell, who sent it to the Linnean Society, and it is published in the third volume of the Journal of that Society. Sir C. Lyell and Dr. Hooker, who both knew of my work--the latter having read my sketch of 1844--honoured me by thinking it advisable to publish, with Mr. Wallace's excellent memoir, some brief extracts from my manuscripts.
   This Abstract, which I now publish, must necessarily be imperfect. I cannot here give references and authorities for my several statements; and I must trust to the reader reposing some confidence in my accuracy. No doubt errors will have crept in, though I hope I have always been cautious in trusting to good authorities alone. I can here give only the general conclusions at which I have arrived, with a few facts in illustration, but which, I hope, in most cases will suffice. No one can feel more sensible than I do of the necessity of hereafter publishing in detail all the facts, with references, on which my conclusions have been grounded; and I hope in a future work to do this. For I am well aware that scarcely a single point is discussed in this volume on which facts cannot be adduced, often apparently leading to conclusions directly opposite to those at which I have arrived. A fair result can be obtained only by fully stating and balancing the facts and arguments on both sides of each question; and this cannot possibly be here done.
   I much regret that want of space prevents my having the satisfaction of acknowledging the generous assistance which I have received from very many naturalists, some of them personally unknown to me. I cannot, however, let this opportunity pass without expressing my deep obligations to Dr. Hooker, who for the last fifteen years has aided me in every possible way by his large stores of knowledge and his excellent judgment.
   In considering the Origin of Species, it is quite conceivable that a naturalist, reflecting on the mutual affinities of organic beings, on their embryological relations, their geographical distribution, geological succession, and other such facts, might come to the conclusion that each species had not been independently created, but had descended, like varieties, from other species. Nevertheless, such a conclusion, even if well founded, would be unsatisfactory, until it could be shown how the innumerable species inhabiting this world have been modified, so as to acquire that perfection of structure and coadaptation which most justly excites our admiration. Naturalists continually refer to external conditions, such as climate, food, etc., as the only possible cause of variation. In one very limited sense, as we shall hereafter see, this may be true; but it is preposterous to attribute to mere external conditions, the structure, for instance, of the woodpecker, with its feet, tail, beak, and tongue, so admirably adapted to catch insects under the bark of trees. In the case of the misseltoe, which draws its nourishment from certain trees, which has seeds that must be transported by certain birds, and which has flowers with separate sexes absolutely requiring the agency of certain insects to bring pollen from one flower to the other, it is equally preposterous to account for the structure of this parasite, with its relations to several distinct organic beings, by the effects of external conditions, or of habit, or of the volition of the plant itself.
   The author of the 'Vestiges of Creation' would, I presume, say that, after a certain unknown number of generations, some bird had given birth to a woodpecker, and some plant to the misseltoe, and that these had been produced perfect as we now see them; but this assumption seems to me to be no explanation, for it leaves the case of the coadaptations of organic beings to each other and to their physical conditions of life, untouched and unexplained.
   It is, therefore, of the highest importance to gain a clear insight into the means of modification and coadaptation. At the commencement of my observations it seemed to me probable that a careful study of domesticated animals and of cultivated plants would offer the best chance of making out this obscure problem. Nor have I been disappointed; in this and in all other perplexing cases I have invariably found that our knowledge, imperfect though it be, of variation under domestication, afforded the best and safest clue. I may venture to express my conviction of the high value of such studies, although they have been very commonly neglected by naturalists.
   From these considerations, I shall devote the first chapter of this Abstract to Variation under Domestication. We shall thus see that a large amount of hereditary modification is at least possible, and, what is equally or more important, we shall see how great is the power of man in accumulating by his Selection successive slight variations. I will then pass on to the variability of species in a state of nature; but I shall, unfortunately, be compelled to treat this subject far too briefly, as it can be treated properly only by giving long catalogues of facts. We shall, however, be enabled to discuss what circumstances are most favourable to variation. In the next chapter the Struggle for Existence amongst all organic beings throughout the world, which inevitably follows from their high geometrical powers of increase, will be treated of. This is the doctrine of Malthus, applied to the whole animal and vegetable kingdoms. As many more individuals of each species are born than can possibly survive; and as, consequently, there is a frequently recurring struggle for existence, it follows that any being, if it vary however slightly in any manner profitable to itself, under the complex and sometimes varying conditions of life, will have a better chance of surviving, and thus be NATURALLY SELECTED. From the strong principle of inheritance, any selected variety will tend to propagate its new and modified form.
   This fundamental subject of Natural Selection will be treated at some length in the fourth chapter; and we shall then see how Natural Selection almost inevitably causes much Extinction of the less improved forms of life and induces what I have called Divergence of Character. In the next chapter I shall discuss the complex and little known laws of variation and of correlation of growth. In the four succeeding chapters, the most apparent and gravest difficulties on the theory will be given: namely, first, the difficulties of transitions, or in understanding how a simple being or a simple organ can be changed and perfected into a highly developed being or elaborately constructed organ; secondly the subject of Instinct, or the mental powers of animals, thirdly, Hybridism, or the infertility of species and the fertility of varieties when intercrossed; and fourthly, the imperfection of the Geological Record. In the next chapter I shall consider the geological succession of organic beings throughout time; in the eleventh and twelfth, their geographical distribution throughout space; in the thirteenth, their classification or mutual affinities, both when mature and in an embryonic condition. In the last chapter I shall give a brief recapitulation of the whole work, and a few concluding remarks.
   No one ought to feel surprise at much remaining as yet unexplained in regard to the origin of species and varieties, if he makes due allowance for our profound ignorance in regard to the mutual relations of all the beings which live around us. Who can explain why one species ranges widely and is very numerous, and why another allied species has a narrow range and is rare? Yet these relations are of the highest importance, for they determine the present welfare, and, as I believe, the future success and modification of every inhabitant of this world. Still less do we know of the mutual relations of the innumerable inhabitants of the world during the many past geological epochs in its history. Although much remains obscure, and will long remain obscure, I can entertain no doubt, after the most deliberate study and dispassionate judgment of which I am capable, that the view which most naturalists entertain, and which I formerly entertained--namely, that each species has been independently created--is erroneous. I am fully convinced that species are not immutable; but that those belonging to what are called the same genera are lineal descendants of some other and generally extinct species, in the same manner as the acknowledged varieties of any one species are the descendants of that species. Furthermore, I am convinced that Natural Selection has been the main but not exclusive means of modification.
  Causes of Variability. Effects of Habit. Correlation of Growth. Inheritance. Character of Domestic Varieties. Difficulty of distinguishing between Varieties and Species. Origin of Domestic Varieties from one or more Species. Domestic Pigeons, their Differences and Origin. Principle of Selection anciently followed, its Effects. Methodical and Unconscious Selection. Unknown Origin of our Domestic Productions. Circumstances favourable to Man's power of Selection.
   When we look to the individuals of the same variety or sub-variety of our older cultivated plants and animals, one of the first points which strikes us, is, that they generally differ much more from each other, than do the individuals of any one species or variety in a state of nature. When we reflect on the vast diversity of the plants and animals which have been cultivated, and which have varied during all ages under the most different climates and treatment, I think we are driven to conclude that this greater variability is simply due to our domestic productions having been raised under conditions of life not so uniform as, and somewhat different from, those to which the parent-species have been exposed under nature. There is, also, I think, some probability in the view propounded by Andrew Knight, that this variability may be partly connected with excess of food. It seems pretty clear that organic beings must be exposed during several generations to the new conditions of life to cause any appreciable amount of variation; and that when the organisation has once begun to vary, it generally continues to vary for many generations. No case is on record of a variable being ceasing to be variable under cultivation. Our oldest cultivated plants, such as wheat, still often yield new varieties: our oldest domesticated animals are still capable of rapid improvement or modification.
   It has been disputed at what period of life the causes of variability, whatever they may be, generally act; whether during the early or late period of development of the embryo, or at the instant of conception. Geoffroy St. Hilaire's experiments show that unnatural treatment of the embryo causes monstrosities; and monstrosities cannot be separated by any clear line of distinction from mere variations. But I am strongly inclined to suspect that the most frequent cause of variability may be attributed to the male and female reproductive elements having been affected prior to the act of conception. Several reasons make me believe in this; but the chief one is the remarkable effect which confinement or cultivation has on the functions of the reproductive system; this system appearing to be far more susceptible than any other part of the organisation, to the action of any change in the conditions of life. Nothing is more easy than to tame an animal, and few things more difficult than to get it to breed freely under confinement, even in the many cases when the male and female unite. How many animals there are which will not breed, though living long under not very close confinement in their native country! This is generally attributed to vitiated instincts; but how many cultivated plants display the utmost vigour, and yet rarely or never seed! In some few such cases it has been found out that very trifling changes, such as a little more or less water at some particular period of growth, will determine whether or not the plant sets a seed. I cannot here enter on the copious details which I have collected on this curious subject; but to show how singular the laws are which determine the reproduction of animals under confinement, I may just mention that carnivorous animals, even from the tropics, breed in this country pretty freely under confinement, with the exception of the plantigrades or bear family; whereas, carnivorous birds, with the rarest exceptions, hardly ever lay fertile eggs. Many exotic plants have pollen utterly worthless, in the same exact condition as in the most sterile hybrids. When, on the one hand, we see domesticated animals and plants, though often weak and sickly, yet breeding quite freely under confinement; and when, on the other hand, we see individuals, though taken young from a state of nature, perfectly tamed, long-lived, and healthy (of which I could give numerous instances), yet having their reproductive system so seriously affected by unperceived causes as to fail in acting, we need not be surprised at this system, when it does act under confinement, acting not quite regularly, and producing offspring not perfectly like their parents or variable.
   Sterility has been said to be the bane of horticulture; but on this view we owe variability to the same cause which produces sterility; and variability is the source of all the choicest productions of the garden. I may add, that as some organisms will breed most freely under the most unnatural conditions (for instance, the rabbit and ferret kept in hutches), showing that their reproductive system has not been thus affected; so will some animals and plants withstand domestication or cultivation, and vary very slightly--perhaps hardly more than in a state of nature.
   A long list could easily be given of "sporting plants;" by this term gardeners mean a single bud or offset, which suddenly assumes a new and sometimes very different character from that of the rest of the plant. Such buds can be propagated by grafting, etc., and sometimes by seed. These "sports" are extremely rare under nature, but far from rare under cultivation; and in this case we see that the treatment of the parent has affected a bud or offset, and not the ovules or pollen. But it is the opinion of most physiologists that there is no essential difference between a bud and an ovule in their earliest stages of formation; so that, in fact, "sports" support my view, that variability may be largely attributed to the ovules or pollen, or to both, having been affected by the treatment of the parent prior to the act of conception. These cases anyhow show that variation is not necessarily connected, as some authors have supposed, with the act of generation.
   Seedlings from the same fruit, and the young of the same litter, sometimes differ considerably from each other, though both the young and the parents, as Muller has remarked, have apparently been exposed to exactly the same conditions of life; and this shows how unimportant the direct effects of the conditions of life are in comparison with the laws of reproduction, and of growth, and of inheritance; for had the action of the conditions been direct, if any of the young had varied, all would probably have varied in the same manner. To judge how much, in the case of any variation, we should attribute to the direct action of heat, moisture, light, food, etc., is most difficult: my impression is, that with animals such agencies have produced very little direct effect, though apparently more in the case of plants. Under this point of view, Mr. Buckman's recent experiments on plants seem extremely valuable. When all or nearly all the individuals exposed to certain conditions are affected in the same way, the change at first appears to be directly due to such conditions; but in some cases it can be shown that quite opposite conditions produce similar changes of structure. Nevertheless some slight amount of change may, I think, be attributed to the direct action of the conditions of life--as, in some cases, increased size from amount of food, colour from particular kinds of food and from light, and perhaps the thickness of fur from climate.
   Habit also has a decided influence, as in the period of flowering with plants when transported from one climate to another. In animals it has a more marked effect; for instance, I find in the domestic duck that the bones of the wing weigh less and the bones of the leg more, in proportion to the whole skeleton, than do the same bones in the wild-duck; and I presume that this change may be safely attributed to the domestic duck flying much less, and walking more, than its wild parent. The great and inherited development of the udders in cows and goats in countries where they are habitually milked, in comparison with the state of these organs in other countries, is another instance of the effect of use. Not a single domestic animal can be named which has not in some country drooping ears; and the view suggested by some authors, that the drooping is due to the disuse of the muscles of the ear, from the animals not being much alarmed by danger, seems probable.
   There are many laws regulating variation, some few of which can be dimly seen, and will be hereafter briefly mentioned. I will here only allude to what may be called correlation of growth. Any change in the embryo or larva will almost certainly entail changes in the mature animal. In monstrosities, the correlations between quite distinct parts are very curious; and many instances are given in Isidore Geoffroy St. Hilaire's great work on this subject. Breeders believe that long limbs are almost always accompanied by an elongated head. Some instances of correlation are quite whimsical; thus cats with blue eyes are invariably deaf; colour and constitutional peculiarities go together, of which many remarkable cases could be given amongst animals and plants. From the facts collected by Heusinger, it appears that white sheep and pigs are differently affected from coloured individuals by certain vegetable poisons. Hairless dogs have imperfect teeth; long-haired and coarse-haired animals are apt to have, as is asserted, long or many horns; pigeons with feathered feet have skin between their outer toes; pigeons with short beaks have small feet, and those with long beaks large feet. Hence, if man goes on selecting, and thus augmenting, any peculiarity, he will almost certainly unconsciously modify other parts of the structure, owing to the mysterious laws of the correlation of growth.
   The result of the various, quite unknown, or dimly seen laws of variation is infinitely complex and diversified. It is well worth while carefully to study the several treatises published on some of our old cultivated plants, as on the hyacinth, potato, even the dahlia, etc.; and it is really surprising to note the endless points in structure and constitution in which the varieties and sub-varieties differ slightly from each other. The whole organisation seems to have become plastic, and tends to depart in some small degree from that of the parental type.
   Any variation which is not inherited is unimportant for us. But the number and diversity of inheritable deviations of structure, both those of slight and those of considerable physiological importance, is endless. Dr. Prosper Lucas's treatise, in two large volumes, is the fullest and the best on this subject. No breeder doubts how strong is the tendency to inheritance: like produces like is his fundamental belief: doubts have been thrown on this principle by theoretical writers alone. When a deviation appears not unfrequently, and we see it in the father and child, we cannot tell whether it may not be due to the same original cause acting on both; but when amongst individuals, apparently exposed to the same conditions, any very rare deviation, due to some extraordinary combination of circumstances, appears in the parent--say, once amongst several million individuals--and it reappears in the child, the mere doctrine of chances almost compels us to attribute its reappearance to inheritance. Every one must have heard of cases of albinism, prickly skin, hairy bodies, etc., appearing in several members of the same family. If strange and rare deviations of structure are truly inherited, less strange and commoner deviations may be freely admitted to be inheritable. Perhaps the correct way of viewing the whole subject, would be, to look at the inheritance of every character whatever as the rule, and non-inheritance as the anomaly.
   The laws governing inheritance are quite unknown; no one can say why the same peculiarity in different individuals of the same species, and in individuals of different species, is sometimes inherited and sometimes not so; why the child often reverts in certain characters to its grandfather or grandmother or other much more remote ancestor; why a peculiarity is often transmitted from one sex to both sexes or to one sex alone, more commonly but not exclusively to the like sex. It is a fact of some little importance to us, that peculiarities appearing in the males of our domestic breeds are often transmitted either exclusively, or in a much greater degree, to males alone. A much more important rule, which I think may be trusted, is that, at whatever period of life a peculiarity first appears, it tends to appear in the offspring at a corresponding age, though sometimes earlier. In many cases this could not be otherwise: thus the inherited peculiarities in the horns of cattle could appear only in the offspring when nearly mature; peculiarities in the silkworm are known to appear at the corresponding caterpillar or cocoon stage. But hereditary diseases and some other facts make me believe that the rule has a wider extension, and that when there is no apparent reason why a peculiarity should appear at any particular age, yet that it does tend to appear in the offspring at the same period at which it first appeared in the parent. I believe this rule to be of the highest importance in explaining the laws of embryology. These remarks are of course confined to the first APPEARANCE of the peculiarity, and not to its primary cause, which may have acted on the ovules or male element; in nearly the same manner as in the crossed offspring from a short-horned cow by a long-horned bull, the greater length of horn, though appearing late in life, is clearly due to the male element.
   Having alluded to the subject of reversion, I may here refer to a statement often made by naturalists--namely, that our domestic varieties, when run wild, gradually but certainly revert in character to their aboriginal stocks. Hence it has been argued that no deductions can be drawn from domestic races to species in a state of nature. I have in vain endeavoured to discover on what decisive facts the above statement has so often and so boldly been made. There would be great difficulty in proving its truth: we may safely conclude that very many of the most strongly-marked domestic varieties could not possibly live in a wild state. In many cases we do not know what the aboriginal stock was, and so could not tell whether or not nearly perfect reversion had ensued. It would be quite necessary, in order to prevent the effects of intercrossing, that only a single variety should be turned loose in its new home. Nevertheless, as our varieties certainly do occasionally revert in some of their characters to ancestral forms, it seems to me not improbable, that if we could succeed in naturalising, or were to cultivate, during many generations, the several races, for instance, of the cabbage, in very poor soil (in which case, however, some effect would have to be attributed to the direct action of the poor soil), that they would to a large extent, or even wholly, revert to the wild aboriginal stock. Whether or not the experiment would succeed, is not of great importance for our line of argument; for by the experiment itself the conditions of life are changed. If it could be shown that our domestic varieties manifested a strong tendency to reversion,--that is, to lose their acquired characters, whilst kept under unchanged conditions, and whilst kept in a considerable body, so that free intercrossing might check, by blending together, any slight deviations of structure, in such case, I grant that we could deduce nothing from domestic varieties in regard to species. But there is not a shadow of evidence in favour of this view: to assert that we could not breed our cart and race-horses, long and short-horned cattle, and poultry of various breeds, and esculent vegetables, for an almost infinite number of generations, would be opposed to all experience. I may add, that when under nature the conditions of life do change, variations and reversions of character probably do occur; but natural selection, as will hereafter be explained, will determine how far the new characters thus arising shall be preserved.
   When we look to the hereditary varieties or races of our domestic animals and plants, and compare them with species closely allied together, we generally perceive in each domestic race, as already remarked, less uniformity of character than in true species. Domestic races of the same species, also, often have a somewhat monstrous character; by which I mean, that, although differing from each other, and from the other species of the same genus, in several trifling respects, they often differ in an extreme degree in some one part, both when compared one with another, and more especially when compared with all the species in nature to which they are nearest allied. With these exceptions (and with that of the perfect fertility of varieties when crossed,--a subject hereafter to be discussed), domestic races of the same species differ from each other in the same manner as, only in most cases in a lesser degree than, do closely-allied species of the same genus in a state of nature. I think this must be admitted, when we find that there are hardly any domestic races, either amongst animals or plants, which have not been ranked by some competent judges as mere varieties, and by other competent judges as the descendants of aboriginally distinct species. If any marked distinction existed between domestic races and species, this source of doubt could not so perpetually recur. It has often been stated that domestic races do not differ from each other in characters of generic value. I think it could be shown that this statement is hardly correct; but naturalists differ most widely in determining what characters are of generic value; all such valuations being at present empirical. Moreover, on the view of the origin of genera which I shall presently give, we have no right to expect often to meet with generic differences in our domesticated productions.
   When we attempt to estimate the amount of structural difference between the domestic races of the same species, we are soon involved in doubt, from not knowing whether they have descended from one or several parent-species. This point, if it could be cleared up, would be interesting; if, for instance, it could be shown that the greyhound, bloodhound, terrier, spaniel, and bull-dog, which we all know propagate their kind so truly, were the offspring of any single species, then such facts would have great weight in making us doubt about the immutability of the many very closely allied and natural species--for instance, of the many foxes--inhabiting different quarters of the world. I do not believe, as we shall presently see, that all our dogs have descended from any one wild species; but, in the case of some other domestic races, there is presumptive, or even strong, evidence in favour of this view.
   It has often been assumed that man has chosen for domestication animals and plants having an extraordinary inherent tendency to vary, and likewise to withstand diverse climates. I do not dispute that these capacities have added largely to the value of most of our domesticated productions; but how could a savage possibly know, when he first tamed an animal, whether it would vary in succeeding generations, and whether it would endure other climates? Has the little variability of the ass or guinea-fowl, or the small power of endurance of warmth by the rein-deer, or of cold by the common camel, prevented their domestication? I cannot doubt that if other animals and plants, equal in number to our domesticated productions, and belonging to equally diverse classes and countries, were taken from a state of nature, and could be made to breed for an equal number of generations under domestication, they would vary on an average as largely as the parent species of our existing domesticated productions have varied.
首頁>> 文學>> 动物>> 達爾文 Charles Darwin   英國 United Kingdom   漢諾威王朝   (1809年二月12日1882年四月19日)